
Why Would Anyone Be Conscious?
11 minIntroduction
Narrator: Imagine being trapped inside your own body, fully aware, your mind as sharp as ever, yet completely unable to move or speak. This was the reality for Jean-Dominique Bauby, the editor-in-chief of French Elle magazine, after a massive stroke left him with locked-in syndrome. His only means of communication was the blink of his left eyelid. To an outside observer, he might have appeared unconscious, a body without a mind. Yet, inside, a rich, vibrant consciousness was experiencing everything—the frustration, the memories, the love for his family. Bauby’s story forces us to confront a terrifying question: how can we ever truly know if another being is conscious? And what is this inner experience, this awareness, in the first place?
This profound mystery is the subject of Annaka Harris’s book, Why Would Anyone Be Conscious?. It dismantles our most basic assumptions about ourselves and reality, guiding us through the bewildering science and philosophy of what it means to have an inner life.
The Hard Problem is a Mystery Hiding in Plain Sight
Key Insight 1
Narrator: The most fundamental mystery of consciousness isn't its function, but its very existence. Philosopher David Chalmers termed this the "hard problem": why do physical processes in the brain produce subjective experience? We are so immersed in our own awareness that we rarely stop to consider how strange it is.
Harris illustrates this with the development of a human being. A microscopic collection of cells, a blastocyst, is presumably not conscious. Yet, through a process of cell division and differentiation, it becomes a baby with a brain. At some point in this process, something miraculous happens. The processing of light and sound is no longer just a physical reaction; it is accompanied by the experience of seeing and hearing. As philosopher Rebecca Goldstein puts it, "Suddenly, matter wakes up and takes in the world?" This transition from non-sentient matter to subjective awareness is as profound as something appearing from nothing. There is no scientific theory that can yet explain how or why this happens. Consciousness is not just another property of matter like mass or charge; it is the fact that it is like something to be that matter.
Our Intuitions About Consciousness Are Deeply Flawed
Key Insight 2
Narrator: We instinctively believe that complex behavior implies consciousness. If something acts aware, we assume it is. Harris argues this intuition is unreliable. Consider the case of plants. Research by forest ecologist Suzanne Simard reveals that trees communicate through vast underground networks, sharing resources and even preferentially nurturing their own kin. They exhibit sophisticated, intelligent behavior, yet we don't assume there is something it is "like" to be a tree.
Conversely, consciousness can exist without any outward behavior at all. The tragic reality of anesthesia awareness, where a patient is paralyzed but fully conscious during surgery, is a horrifying example. The case of Jean-Dominique Bauby, who painstakingly wrote his memoir by blinking his eye, proves that a rich inner world can persist in a completely unresponsive body. These examples sever the link we intuitively draw between action and awareness. Behavior, Harris concludes, is not a reliable guide for detecting consciousness.
Consciousness is Not the Captain of the Ship
Key Insight 3
Narrator: Our sense of being in control, of consciously willing our actions, is a powerful feeling. However, neuroscience suggests it may be an illusion. The famous experiments by neuroscientist Benjamin Libet in the 1980s provided the first major challenge to this idea. Using EEG to monitor brain activity, Libet found that the brain initiates preparations for a voluntary movement—like flicking a wrist—a full half-second before the person reports consciously deciding to move. Consciousness, it seems, is the last to know.
This idea is further supported by the bizarre influence of parasites. The single-celled organism Toxoplasma gondii can only reproduce inside a cat. To get there, it infects rats and alters their brain chemistry, making them lose their innate fear of cats and even become attracted to their scent. The rat is no longer acting in its own best interest; its behavior is being driven by an external agent. Harris uses these examples to argue that consciousness may often be "along for the ride," a passenger that witnesses decisions and actions rather than initiating them. The feeling of free will, she suggests, is a story the brain tells itself after the fact.
The "Self" is a Fleeting Construct
Key Insight 4
Narrator: Just as our sense of control is an illusion, so too is our sense of a stable, unified "self." Harris points to split-brain research as compelling evidence. In patients who have had the connection between their brain's two hemispheres severed, it's possible to communicate with each hemisphere independently. In one famous experiment, the instruction "Take a walk" was flashed to a patient's right hemisphere. The patient stood up and started walking. When asked why, his left hemisphere—which controls speech and was unaware of the command—confidently invented a reason: "Oh, I need to get a drink." Neuroscientist Michael Gazzaniga calls the left hemisphere "the interpreter," a module that constantly creates a coherent narrative to explain our actions, even if that narrative is false.
This feeling of a unified self can also be dissolved. Studies on psilocybin, the psychoactive compound in magic mushrooms, show that it decreases activity in the brain's "default mode network," an area associated with self-referential thought. Participants often report a profound loss of their sense of self, describing a feeling of merging with the world around them. Consciousness remains, but the "I" at its center disappears. This suggests the self is not the core of consciousness, but rather a specific pattern of brain activity that can be turned on and off.
Consciousness Might Be a Fundamental Property of the Universe
Key Insight 5
Narrator: If consciousness doesn't seem to do much, if free will and the self are illusions, and if it's impossible to explain how it emerges from non-conscious matter, then perhaps we are looking at the problem backward. This leads to one of the book's most mind-bending ideas: panpsychism. Panpsychism is the theory that consciousness is not a special property of complex brains but a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of matter itself.
This doesn't mean a rock is thinking about philosophy. Rather, it suggests that even an electron possesses some primitive, unimaginably simple form of experience. Just as particles have properties like mass and spin, they may also have an intrinsic "experiential" property. From this perspective, the complex consciousness of a human brain isn't something that magically appears from nothing. Instead, it's a complex combination of the rudimentary consciousness that was already present in its constituent particles. As strange as it sounds, many philosophers and scientists argue that this is a more parsimonious and scientifically elegant explanation than the "radical emergence" of awareness from completely inert matter.
The Observer's Paradox Bends Time and Reality
Key Insight 6
Narrator: The book's final exploration delves into the relationship between consciousness, time, and the bizarre world of quantum physics. Our experience of time as a flowing river from past to future is not supported by modern physics. One theory, eternalism, suggests that all moments in time—past, present, and future—exist simultaneously, much like locations in space.
This idea becomes even stranger with experiments like physicist John Wheeler's "delayed-choice" experiment. In a quantum system, a particle like a photon can behave as either a particle or a wave. The act of measuring it determines its state. Wheeler's thought experiment, later confirmed in labs, showed that the choice to measure the photon's path after it has already completed its journey can retroactively determine what path it took in the past. An observation made in the present appears to shape a past event. This suggests a deep and mysterious link between observation—an act of consciousness—and the very fabric of reality. The mystery of consciousness, Harris concludes, may be inextricably linked to the deepest mysteries of the cosmos itself.
Conclusion
Narrator: The journey through Why Would Anyone Be Conscious? leaves us with the profound realization that our intuitive understanding of our own minds is almost certainly wrong. The book argues that consciousness is not the executive controller we imagine it to be, the self is a fragile illusion, and awareness itself might be a fundamental property woven into the universe. The single most important takeaway is that we must approach the mystery of consciousness with humility, questioning our most deeply held beliefs about who we are.
This exploration is not merely a philosophical exercise. As we stand on the cusp of creating advanced artificial intelligence, the question of whether a machine can be conscious is one of the most critical ethical challenges of our time. Harris’s work forces us to ask: If we don't even understand the nature of our own consciousness, how can we ever hope to recognize it—or fail to recognize it—in another being?