
Why Aristotle Categorized His Soul
15 minGolden Hook & Introduction
SECTION
Michael: Alright Kevin, quick improv game. I say a classic philosopher, you give me the title of their terrible, modern self-help book. Ready? Plato. Kevin: Plato... "Unfriend Your Cave-Mates: How to See the Light and Annoy Everyone You Know." Michael: (Laughs) Perfect. Okay, next one: Nietzsche. Kevin: "Embrace the Void: A 7-Step Guide to Becoming Your Own Over-Caffeinated Superman." Michael: I would buy that in a heartbeat. Last one, the big boss himself: Aristotle. Kevin: Oh, Aristotle. That's easy. "Categorize Your Sock Drawer, Categorize Your Soul: Finding Purpose in Extreme Organization." Michael: That is painfully accurate. And it’s that impulse—to categorize, to understand, to find the fundamental 'why' behind everything—that brings us to the book we’re tackling today. It's not a self-help book, but it might be the ultimate book about the 'self' of everything. We are diving into the deep end with Metaphysics by Aristotle. Kevin: The Mount Everest of philosophy books. I feel like I should be wearing tweed and looking thoughtful just saying the title. And Aristotle isn't just some random ancient thinker; this is the guy who tutored Alexander the Great. He basically invented half the fields we study today—logic, biology, ethics... Michael: Exactly. And what's fascinating about the Metaphysics is that it wasn't really a 'book' in the way we think of one. It’s a compilation of his lecture notes, probably put together by his students after he died. That's why it's famously difficult and sometimes feels disjointed. We're essentially reading the raw, unfiltered thoughts of one of history's greatest minds as he wrestles with the biggest questions imaginable. Kevin: So it’s less of a polished TED Talk and more like peeking at his messy whiteboard full of scribbled genius. I like that. It feels more authentic. So, where do we even start with a book that tries to explain... well, everything?
The Quest for 'First Philosophy': What Are We Even Talking About?
SECTION
Michael: We start where he does, with a very simple, very human feeling: wonder. Aristotle opens Book Alpha with the line, "By nature, all men long to know." He believed philosophy begins when we stop just dealing with the practical stuff and start asking, "Wait, why is there stuff at all? What does it mean for something to be?" Kevin: That's a question that can send you into an existential spiral pretty quickly. Most of us are just trying to figure out what to have for dinner. Why was he so obsessed with this abstract level of 'being'? Michael: Because he saw a crucial difference between different kinds of knowledge. He uses a great example: the doctor. You have two kinds of doctors. The first is the 'man of experience'. He knows that when Callias has a certain fever, a specific herb works. When Socrates has the same fever, that herb works too. He knows that it works for individuals, but he doesn't know why. Kevin: He's got the practical skill. He can cure the patient in front of him, which, as a patient, is all I really care about. Michael: Exactly. But then you have the second doctor, the 'man of art or science'. This doctor understands the universal principle. She knows that this type of fever, in all phlegmatic people, is cured by this herb. She understands the cause. Aristotle says this second person is wiser, because they have universal knowledge. And the ultimate wisdom, what he calls 'First Philosophy' or 'Metaphysics', is the science of the most universal thing of all: being itself. Kevin: Hold on, "the science of being qua being." That phrase sounds incredibly intimidating. What does 'qua' even mean? Is it a fancy Greek almond? Michael: (Laughs) It's a philosopher's ten-dollar word for 'as'. He wants to study 'being as being'. Think of it this way: a biologist studies being, but only as it relates to living things. A physicist studies being, but only as it relates to matter and motion. Aristotle wanted a science that studied being... just for being. What are the rules that apply to everything that exists, simply because it exists? Kevin: Okay, so not 'what is a tree?' but 'what does it mean for the tree to be a tree, or for anything to be anything?' That feels... profoundly useless. Michael: He would agree with you! He says this is the most divine and most useless of all sciences. It won't help you build a better chariot or make more money. Its entire purpose is understanding for its own sake. He points to the development of mathematics in ancient Egypt. It arose because the priestly caste had leisure time. Once all the necessary and pleasurable arts were taken care of, they could finally pursue knowledge that served no practical purpose. For Aristotle, that's the pinnacle of human achievement. Kevin: So it's a luxury good for the mind. You can only afford to wonder about the nature of reality after you've figured out irrigation and invented beer. Michael: Precisely. And this quest led him to believe that if you want to understand 'being', you first have to understand 'cause'. You can't know the truth of something, he says, without knowing its cause. And that leads us to his most famous and practical tool for dissecting reality. Kevin: Ah, I feel a list coming on. This is where the sock-drawer categorization comes in, isn't it? Michael: It is. But it's a list that, once you see it, you'll start seeing it everywhere. He argues there aren't a million types of causes, just four fundamental ones.
The Four Causes: Aristotle's Toolkit for Understanding Everything
SECTION
Kevin: Okay, lay it on me. What is Aristotle's four-part toolkit for explaining literally everything in the universe? Michael: These are the Four Causes. Let's use your coffee mug as our test subject. The first is the Material Cause: what is it made of? For your mug, it's ceramic. Simple enough. Kevin: Got it. The stuff. Michael: The second is the Formal Cause: what is its form, its essence, its blueprint? It's the 'mug-ness' of the mug. It’s the shape, the design that makes it a mug and not a plate. It’s the idea the potter had in their head. Kevin: The blueprint. The structure. Okay. Michael: The third is the Efficient Cause: what is the primary source of the change or its coming-into-being? This is the potter who shaped the clay, the kiln that fired it. It's the agent that made the thing happen. Kevin: The doer. The thing that pushed it into existence. Michael: Exactly. And finally, the fourth and, for Aristotle, often the most important, is the Final Cause: what is the purpose, the end, the 'for the sake of which' a thing exists? For the mug, its purpose is to hold coffee so you can drink it. Kevin: To contain liquid. So, we have: what it's made of, what it's shaped like, who made it, and what it's for. Material, Formal, Efficient, Final. Michael: You've got it. And Aristotle believed that every single thing, from a statue to a tree to a human being, could be fully understood by analyzing it through these four lenses. He actually uses this framework to critique all the philosophers who came before him. Kevin: How so? Michael: He says most of the early philosophers, like Thales who thought everything was made of water, were only thinking about the Material Cause. They were just asking "what's the world's stuff?" Then, thinkers like Anaxagoras came along and proposed 'Mind' as an ordering principle, or Empedocles proposed 'Love' and 'Strife'. Aristotle says, "Aha! They were fumbling towards the Efficient Cause—the source of motion—but they didn't do it clearly." Kevin: And Plato, with his world of perfect Forms? Michael: That's the Formal Cause! Plato was obsessed with the perfect blueprint of 'treeness' or 'justice'. But Aristotle's big critique of Plato, which is a huge part of the Metaphysics, is that Plato's Forms are just a shadow world. They don't do anything. They don't explain change or purpose. They're like a blueprint with no builder and no reason to build the house. Kevin: So Aristotle's four causes are his attempt to create a complete, unified theory of explanation that his predecessors only saw pieces of. It’s actually a pretty elegant system. It feels very complete. Michael: It does, but it leads him into his biggest, most complex, and most profound problem. Once you have this toolkit, you have to apply it to the biggest question of all: what is the most fundamental thing that is? What is 'substance'? And this is where the book gets really wild.
The Problem of Substance: What Is 'Real' Anyway?
SECTION
Kevin: Okay, 'substance'. When I hear that word, I think of something physical, something I can touch. Like, this desk is a substance. Michael: That's exactly where Aristotle starts in his earlier work, the Categories. He says primary substances are individual things: this man, this horse. Socrates is a substance. Your desk is a substance. They are the fundamental subjects that have properties. The desk is brown; brown isn't a substance, it's a quality of the desk. Kevin: That makes perfect, intuitive sense. The world is made up of a bunch of individual things. End of story, right? Michael: Not for Aristotle. In the Metaphysics, he creates a huge crisis for himself. He realizes that if you want to explain change—a core part of reality—then individual things can't be the whole story. Think about it: what happens when Socrates dies? The individual, Socrates, is gone. But something persists. The matter he was made of is still there. Kevin: Right, the atoms and molecules just get rearranged. Michael: Exactly. This leads to a terrifying thought for a Greek philosopher: if the underlying matter is what's truly fundamental, and matter itself has no form or definition, then is reality ultimately just a pile of unintelligible goop? Is the world, at its core, unknowable? Kevin: That's a dark turn. So he's stuck. If the individual is the substance, you can't explain change. If matter is the substance, you can't explain... well, anything. The world becomes meaningless chaos. Michael: This is the central drama of Book Zeta, which is considered the heart of the Metaphysics. He's searching for something that can be both the fundamental bedrock of reality and the root of its intelligibility. He runs through the candidates: is it the subject (the individual)? Is it the matter? Or is it the essence—the 'what-it-was-to-be-that-thing'? Kevin: The 'what-it-was-to-be-that-thing'? He really needed a better marketing department. Michael: (Laughs) He did. But it's a brilliant concept. The essence is what's captured in the definition of something. The essence of a mug is 'a vessel for drinking'. He argues that this essence, or the form, is the true substance. And this leads him to a radical conclusion, completely overturning his earlier work. He decides that the ultimate substance isn't the individual, Socrates, but the species: Man. Kevin: Wait, what? So the 'idea' of a human is more real than an actual human? That sounds suspiciously like he's circling right back to Plato's Forms, the very thing he was criticizing. Michael: It's the great debate among Aristotle scholars! Is he relapsing into Platonism? He tries to fight his way out of it. He argues that a species, like 'Man' or 'Horse', isn't a universal in the same way Plato's Forms are. He uses this idea of 'thisness'. You can point to a picture of a dog breed in a catalogue and say "I want this one," and you're referring to the species, not a specific dog. He argues species have a kind of concrete reality that universals like 'redness' don't. Kevin: My brain hurts. He seems to be tying himself in logical knots. Does he ever actually solve it? Michael: That's the beauty of the Metaphysics. In a later book, Book Eta, he seems to swing back again, trying to find a way to say that the composite individual—the form and matter together, Socrates himself—is the true substance after all. He introduces concepts of 'potentiality' and 'actuality' to try and resolve it. The book isn't a final answer; it's the record of a brilliant mind wrestling with the problem from every possible angle. Kevin: So the value isn't in the final, neat conclusion, but in the struggle itself. It's about the quality of the questions he's asking. Michael: Precisely. The history of metaphysics is often called a history of "magnificent failures." The arguments are so profound and fascinating that they're valuable even if their conclusions aren't provably correct. Aristotle is trying to build a system that accounts for three things at once: that real things exist, that they can change, and that we can understand them. Holding all three of those truths at the same time is the fundamental challenge of his work, and maybe of all philosophy.
Synthesis & Takeaways
SECTION
Kevin: So, after all this, what's the big takeaway? We've gone from wondering about 'being' to a four-part toolkit for reality, and ended up in a deep, confusing debate about what's even real. Michael: I think the biggest takeaway is about the nature of understanding itself. Aristotle shows us that a deep inquiry into the world requires moving beyond simple, practical knowledge. He gives us a framework—the four causes—that pushes us to look at things from multiple perspectives: their material, their design, their origin, and their purpose. Kevin: It’s a call to think more deeply about the 'why' behind everything, not just the 'what' or 'how'. Even for my coffee mug, asking about its final cause—its purpose—is a fundamentally different kind of question than asking what it's made of. Michael: Exactly. And his struggle with 'substance' is so powerful because it mirrors a very modern anxiety. In a world that science tells us is just atoms and void, what makes an individual thing, or a person, real and meaningful? Aristotle was wrestling with that over two thousand years ago. He was trying to find a philosophical basis for a world that was both material and meaningful, a world of change that was also understandable. Kevin: And the fact that the Metaphysics is this collection of raw, sometimes contradictory notes makes that struggle feel more honest. We're not getting a polished sermon; we're watching the philosophical workout. Michael: That's a perfect way to put it. He leaves us with a profound challenge. He says the ultimate cause, the 'Unmoved Mover' that is the final cause of all motion in the universe, is a being of pure actuality—pure thought, thinking about itself. And the most human, most divine thing we can do is to engage in that same activity: pure contemplation, the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake. Kevin: So, the purpose of life, in a way, is to sit down and try to read books like the Metaphysics. That's a very convenient conclusion for a philosopher to reach. But I get it. The act of trying to understand is what makes us who we are. For anyone listening who feels that pull of wonder, that desire to ask the big 'why' questions, this book is a monumental starting point. We'd love to hear your thoughts. Have you tried to climb Mount Aristotle? What did you find? Let us know. Michael: This is Aibrary, signing off.