
Jean-Paul Sartre’s Being and Nothingness Class Lecture Notes
10 minIntroduction
Narrator: A waiter moves through a bustling Parisian café. His movements are a little too precise, a little too rapid. He bends forward a little too eagerly, his voice expressing an interest a little too solicitous for the customer's order. He seems to be playing at being a waiter, imitating the inflexible stiffness of an automaton. He is not just doing a job; he is trying to be a waiter, to embody the role so completely that it consumes him. Why would someone try so hard to become a thing they already are? This strange performance is not just a curiosity; it is a profound act of self-deception that lies at the heart of our human condition. In his comprehensive lecture notes on Jean-Paul Sartre’s monumental work, Being and Nothingness, Paul Vincent Spade provides a detailed map to navigate Sartre's complex and often unsettling exploration of freedom, responsibility, and the stories we tell ourselves to escape them.
The Two Realms of Reality: Consciousness and The World
Key Insight 1
Narrator: Sartre’s philosophy begins by splitting reality into two fundamentally different domains. The first is being-in-itself. This is the realm of objects—the inert, solid, and unconscious world. A rock, a table, or a tree are all beings-in-themselves. They are simply what they are; they have no awareness, no potential, and no purpose beyond their brute existence. They are completely full of themselves, lacking nothing.
The second domain is being-for-itself, which is consciousness. Unlike the in-itself, consciousness is not a thing. Sartre describes it as a "nothingness" or a "lack." It is not a static object but a dynamic activity. Consciousness is always reaching out beyond itself, directed toward the objects of the world. To illustrate this, Spade uses the analogy of a movie theater. The blank, passive screen is like being-in-itself. It simply exists. The projector's light, which illuminates the screen and gives it form and meaning, is like being-for-itself. Consciousness doesn't create the world, but it illuminates it, organizes it, and brings negation into it. Without the light of consciousness, the world of the in-itself would remain an undifferentiated, meaningless mass. This fundamental split is the foundation for Sartre's entire analysis of the human condition.
The Anguish of Absolute Freedom
Key Insight 2
Narrator: For Sartre, human beings are the embodiment of being-for-itself. The most defining characteristic of this existence is its radical freedom. He famously declares that for humans, "existence precedes essence." This is best understood through his analogy of a letter-opener. An artisan designs a letter-opener with a specific purpose and blueprint in mind—its essence precedes its existence. Humans, however, are not like this. According to Sartre, there is no divine artisan or pre-ordained human nature. We are thrown into the world without a script or a purpose. We simply exist first, and then, through our choices and actions, we create our own essence.
This means we are completely and totally free. However, this freedom is not a gift but a condemnation. It is a source of profound anguish. To illustrate this, Spade points to Sartre's example of a compulsive gambler. The gambler, seeing the ruin his addiction has caused his family, makes a sincere and heartfelt resolution to quit forever. But the next day, when he approaches the gaming table, he realizes with horror that his past resolution is powerless. It is just a memory, an object he can observe. It does not and cannot compel his present self. He is just as free to gamble now as he was to make the resolution yesterday. He must remake the choice ex nihilo—out of nothing. This terrifying awareness that nothing can determine our choices, not even our past selves, is the experience of anguish.
Bad Faith: The Lie We Tell Ourselves to Escape Freedom
Key Insight 3
Narrator: The anguish of absolute freedom is so unbearable that humans constantly try to escape it. The primary mechanism for this escape is what Sartre calls bad faith, or self-deception. Bad faith is a lie we tell ourselves to hide our freedom. We do this by pretending we are not free consciousness (for-itself) but are instead fixed objects (in-itself).
This brings us back to the waiter in the café. His exaggerated performance is an act of bad faith. To understand it, we must grasp Sartre’s concepts of facticity and transcendence. Facticity refers to the brute facts of our situation—our past, our body, our social role. The man is, in fact, a waiter. Transcendence is our freedom to go beyond these facts, to interpret them, and to not be defined by them. The waiter is in bad faith because he denies his transcendence. He tries to become nothing but a waiter, to fuse his entire being with his social function. He acts as if his role determines his every move, turning himself into an automaton. By doing so, he attempts to escape the dizzying responsibility of being a free man who just happens to be a waiter. This is a pattern we all engage in, pretending our jobs, our personalities, or our pasts are fixed essences that define us, rather than facts we are free to transcend.
The Look: How Others Define Us
Key Insight 4
Narrator: Sartre argues that the existence of other people is not something we prove with logic, but something we experience directly and often painfully. This experience is "The Look." To explain this, he tells the story of a man peeping through a keyhole, driven by jealousy or curiosity. In that moment, the world is his alone, a collection of objects organized around his consciousness. He is a pure subject. But then, he hears a footstep in the hall. He realizes he is being seen.
In an instant, everything changes. The world shatters and reorganizes itself around another center: the Other who is looking at him. The man is no longer a subject; he has become an object in someone else's world. He feels himself as he imagines the Other sees him—vulgar, jealous, an object of judgment. This experience of being seen by another consciousness is shame. It reveals a dimension of his being that he cannot control: his being-for-others. This is the core of Sartre's famous statement, "Hell is other people." The inescapable gaze of others constantly threatens to turn us into objects, freezing our possibilities and defining us in ways we cannot escape. Our relationships are thus a fundamental conflict, a struggle between trying to maintain our own subjectivity and being objectified by the Look of the Other.
Existential Psychoanalysis: Uncovering Our Fundamental Choice
Key Insight 5
Narrator: Given this complex view of consciousness, how can we understand an individual's life? Sartre critiques traditional Freudian psychoanalysis for explaining behavior through universal, deterministic principles like the Oedipus complex. He argues this approach reduces a unique individual to a mere intersection of general laws.
As an alternative, Sartre sketches out Existential Psychoanalysis. Its goal is not to uncover a hidden unconscious, but to discover the individual's original project. This is the fundamental, pre-reflective choice of being that a person makes, which gives a unifying meaning to all their seemingly disparate desires and actions. For example, one person's desire for a particular food, their career choice, and their taste in art are not random; they are all expressions of a single, original project—the way that person has chosen to be in the world. This project is the individual's unique attempt to overcome their inherent "lack" and become a self-caused, complete being, an impossible synthesis Sartre calls "being God." While the desire to be God is universal, the way each person chooses to pursue this impossible goal is absolutely unique and free. The task of existential psychoanalysis is to trace these choices back to reveal that original, foundational choice for which the individual is entirely responsible.
Conclusion
Narrator: The single most important takeaway from Sartre's Being and Nothingness is that human beings are radically free, and with that freedom comes total responsibility. We are "condemned to be free," thrown into a world without inherent meaning or a pre-defined nature. We cannot appeal to a divine plan, human nature, or an unconscious mind to excuse our actions. Every moment, we are choosing who we are, and the weight of this creation is ours alone. Our lives are nothing more and nothing less than the sum of our acts.
Sartre's philosophy, as detailed in Spade's notes, is not merely a description of despair but a profound and challenging call to authenticity. It reveals how easily we fall into "bad faith," deceiving ourselves to feel the comfort of being a thing rather than the anguish of being a freedom. The ultimate challenge, then, is to live without these excuses. Can we face the vertigo of our own possibilities and consciously choose our values, our projects, and our very selves? Sartre leaves us with this difficult question, urging us to embrace the terrifying, magnificent responsibility of being the sole author of our own lives.