Aibrary Logo
Podcast thumbnail

Free Agents

10 min

How Evolution Gave Us Free Will

Introduction

Narrator: What if you are not the one in control? Imagine your life is a sophisticated video game. You feel like you’re Player One, making choices, exploring the world, and driving the story forward. But what if you’re actually a Non-Player Character, an NPC? What if your every action, every thought, every desire is simply the output of complex programming—a combination of your genetic code and your life’s experiences? This unsettling thought experiment lies at the heart of the modern debate on free will, where many neuroscientists and physicists argue that our sense of agency is merely a convincing illusion. They claim our brains are just physical machines, and our choices are determined by the laws of physics long before we are consciously aware of them.

But in his book Free Agents: How Evolution Gave Us Free Will, neuroscientist Kevin J. Mitchell presents a powerful counter-argument. He contends that to find the origins of free will, we must look not to the mysteries of quantum physics or the complexities of human consciousness alone, but to the very definition of life itself. Mitchell embarks on an evolutionary journey, revealing how agency—the ability to do things for a reason—is not a late addition to the human mind but a fundamental property that has been evolving for billions of years.

Agency Is the Defining Feature of Life

Key Insight 1

Narrator: The debate about free will often starts with the human brain, but Mitchell argues that this is the wrong place to begin. The story of agency starts with the first living cell. Life, he explains, is not a state but a process—an unending battle against the second law of thermodynamics, which dictates that all things tend toward disorder. To stay alive, an organism must actively work to maintain its own organization. This constant effort gives life its most basic, inherent purpose: to persist.

This is where agency begins. Even the simplest organisms are not passive objects buffeted by their environment. Consider the bacterium E. coli. It doesn't just drift aimlessly. It has evolved sensors to detect gradients of food in the water. When it senses a higher concentration of sugar, it adjusts the rotation of its flagella to swim in that direction. When the concentration drops, it tumbles randomly to find a new path. This isn't a simple reflex; the bacterium is integrating information over time, making a comparison, and acting on an inference about its world. It is doing something for a reason: to get to the food and continue to exist. This is the dawn of agency. The information it gathers has meaning because it is relevant to the organism's fundamental purpose of survival.

The Brain Evolved Not Just to React, but to Predict and Choose

Key Insight 2

Narrator: As life became more complex, so did agency. The evolution of multicellular organisms required new ways to coordinate action. This led to the development of the nervous system, a network for rapid, long-distance communication. Early nervous systems, like the simple nerve net of a Hydra, allowed for basic coordinated movements like contracting or feeding. But as organisms evolved, so did their brains, which became increasingly sophisticated information-processing machines.

Mitchell highlights the nematode worm, C. elegans, as a crucial step. With just 302 neurons, this tiny worm demonstrates a remarkable degree of agency. It doesn't just react to stimuli; it can learn and remember. If it encounters a particular smell paired with food, it will learn to approach it. If that same smell is later paired with a noxious stimulus, it will learn to avoid it. The worm is not just following a rigid program; its experiences reconfigure its neural circuits, allowing it to develop its own reasons for choosing one action over another. Its brain is building a simple model of the world and using that model to make predictions and guide its choices. This evolution toward building internal models of the world, which decouple perception from immediate action, is the foundation for higher-level cognition and, eventually, human consciousness.

Quantum Indeterminacy Creates Causal Slack for the Mind to Act

Key Insight 3

Narrator: One of the biggest challenges to free will comes from physics. If the universe is deterministic, meaning every event is necessitated by prior causes and the laws of nature, then our choices are an illusion. The future, like the past, is already written. Mitchell confronts this head-on by turning to quantum mechanics. He argues that, at the most fundamental level, the universe is not rigidly determined. Quantum physics shows that the future is inherently probabilistic, not certain.

This doesn't mean that random quantum events are "making" our choices for us. That would be just as fatal to free will as determinism. Instead, Mitchell proposes that quantum indeterminacy creates "causal slack." Because the low-level physical details of our brain are not rigidly fixed from one moment to the next, a space opens up for higher-level phenomena to exert causal influence. This means that the system as a whole—the entire organism, with its history, its knowledge, its goals, and its purposes—can constrain and guide the outcome of events. The indeterminacy at the bottom allows for genuine causation from the top. The mind isn't violating the laws of physics; it's harnessing the causal slack built into them.

Meaning, Not Just Mechanism, Drives Our Actions

Key Insight 4

Narrator: If higher-level phenomena can have causal power, what are they? Mitchell's answer is simple: meaning. He uses the analogy of a computer program. A program is an abstract set of rules, but when it runs on a computer, it dictates the flow of electrons through the circuits. The abstract logic—the meaning of the code—is causing physical events to happen. He argues the human brain works in a similar way.

Our thoughts, beliefs, goals, and memories are not ethereal ghosts; they are physically instantiated as complex patterns of neural activity. These patterns have causal power because of what they mean. When you decide to make a cup of tea, that decision is a high-level pattern of neural activity. That pattern, which represents your goal, your memory of tea, and your plan to get it, constrains the firing of other neurons, which in turn activate your muscles to walk to the kitchen and turn on the kettle. The mechanism is physical, but the driver is the meaning. This is how mental causation becomes a real, natural phenomenon, not a magical one. We are not just a "vast assembly of nerve cells," as some reductionists claim; we are a system configured to run on meaning.

Freedom Isn't the Absence of Constraints; It's Being Guided by Your Own

Key Insight 5

Narrator: The final challenge to free will is biological determinism: the idea that our choices are dictated by our genes and past experiences. Are we free if our character and desires were shaped by forces beyond our control? Mitchell argues this is a misunderstanding of both freedom and the self. He asks us to consider what it would mean to be free of all constraints. To have no memories, no personality, no values, no goals. Such a being wouldn't be free; it wouldn't be a "self" at all. It would act randomly, without reason or purpose.

The constraints of our biology and our history are not the enemies of freedom; they are the very things that constitute our identity. Our genes and development give us our innate predispositions. Our experiences, and the choices we make in response to them, build our habits, heuristics, and policies. Together, these form our character. True freedom, Mitchell concludes, is the ability of this self—this coherent, continuous being—to exercise conscious, rational control over its actions. It is the capacity to reason about our reasons, to evaluate our desires, and to choose actions that align with our long-term goals and values. This capacity is the pinnacle of the evolution of agency.

Conclusion

Narrator: Ultimately, Free Agents dismantles the idea that free will is an all-or-nothing illusion. Kevin J. Mitchell's most crucial takeaway is that free will is an evolved, biological function. It is the capacity for a living organism, acting as a unified whole, to make choices and exert conscious, rational control over its actions for its own reasons. This capacity is not magical or absolute; it is a power that depends on the proper functioning of our neural hardware, a power that varies between individuals and can be developed or impaired.

This perspective shifts the entire debate. The question is no longer whether we have free will, but rather how well we are exercising the freedom we have. It challenges us to move beyond fatalistic arguments about determinism and instead embrace the responsibility that comes with being a true agent—a conscious creator of our own actions and, ultimately, our own character.

00:00/00:00